抗核抗体谱检测查什么的| 视野是什么意思| 可乐鸡翅需要什么材料| 梦见着大火了是什么征兆| 花开花落不见你回头是什么歌| 羊肉和什么菜搭配最好| 咬牙齿是什么原因| 定亲是什么意思| 什么坚果适合减肥吃| 令香是什么意思| 淋巴结反应性增生是什么意思| 啤酒酵母是什么| 1946年属什么| 梦到绿色的蛇是什么意思| 真菌性龟头炎用什么药| 钧鉴是什么意思| 为什么拉黑色的屎| 幽门螺旋杆菌阳性什么症状| 小肝功能是检查什么| 怀孕有什么感觉| 吃什么可以去脂肪肝| 灰太狼是什么意思| 朱雀玄武是什么意思| leonardo是什么牌子| 熬夜到什么程度会猝死| 北豆腐是什么| 舐犊是什么意思| 眩晕症是什么原因引起的| 是什么梗| 低血压吃什么| 俄罗斯是什么国家| 血小板少是什么病| 马镫什么时候发明的| 诸葛亮老婆叫什么名字| 仙人跳什么意思| 毛细血管扩张是什么原因引起的| 什么病不能吃豆制品| 烤麸是什么做的| 什么人不适合吃胃复春| 鲁班姓什么| 小狗的尾巴有什么作用| 诗经又称什么| 突然心慌是什么原因| 手背有痣代表什么意思| sheep是什么意思| 吃月饼是什么节日| 孔子名叫什么| vave是什么意思| 扬州有什么特产| 规培是什么| 胃痛吃什么药效果最好| 父母都没有狐臭为什么孩子会有呢| 喝莓茶有什么好处| 怀孕的最佳时间是什么时候| 灭吐灵又叫什么名字| 肺大泡是什么意思| 改户口需要什么手续| 肤色黑穿什么颜色| 什么是借读生| 一九七一年属什么生肖| 每天吃一个西红柿有什么好处| 安眠穴在什么位置| 金蟾吃什么| 不明觉厉是什么意思| 坤宁宫是干什么的| 支气管炎吃什么消炎药| 生命的本质是什么| 吃什么东西减肥| 睡前吃什么有助于睡眠| 吃什么长指甲最快| 1936年中国发生了什么| 盆腔炎是什么引起的| 左什么结构| 一个虫一个离念什么| 腿膝盖后面的窝窝疼是什么原因| 鹦鹉鱼吃什么| 什么是真菌| 梦到吃苹果是什么意思| 窈窕淑女君子好逑是什么意思| 生地和熟地有什么区别| 乳清粉是什么东西| 脸浮肿是什么病的前兆| 卵泡期什么意思| 唐氏筛查是检查什么| 旻字五行属什么| 乌鸦飞进家里什么征兆| 怀孕胸部会有什么反应| 肾不好吃什么好| 肾虚吃什么| 声讨是什么意思| 凶是什么生肖| ig什么意思| 得了甲亢都有什么症状| 邮电局是干什么的| 中产家庭的标准是什么| 南辕北辙是什么故事| pu是什么皮| 为什么右眼一直跳| 羊水偏多是什么原因| 女人什么时候最容易怀孕| qs什么意思| 胸膜炎是什么病| 敷设是什么意思| ovs是什么品牌| 双侧筛窦粘膜增厚是什么意思| 低氧血症是什么意思| 漫谈是什么意思| 普高和职高有什么区别| 治疗白斑最有效的方法是什么| 潮热是什么意思| 腰酸是什么原因引起的| 派大星是什么动物| 表虚自汗是什么意思| 幡是什么意思| 大难不死的生肖是什么| 木薯是什么东西| 智齿长什么样子| 假如时光倒流我能做什么| 广州有什么特产| 系少一撇叫什么| 太白金星叫什么| 人体成分分析是检查什么| 八字加一笔是什么字| 梦见狗咬别人是什么意思| 身上有白斑块是什么原因造成的| 包饺子什么馅好吃| 拉拉是什么意思| 岔气吃什么药最管用| 蔻驰香水属于什么档次| 蜂蜜不能和什么一起吃| est是什么意思| 民间故事有什么| 抗美援朝什么时候结束| 2月23号是什么星座| 胎儿股骨长是什么意思| 憋屎会造成什么后果| 小孩子注意力不集中看什么科| 嗓子有异物感堵得慌吃什么药| 海鸥手表属于什么档次| 纳米是什么东西| 喉咙溃疡吃什么药| 女女叫什么| 孕妇适合吃什么食物| 为什么我的眼里常含泪水| 扁平疣挂什么科| 胎心停了是什么原因引起的| 染色体是什么| 痒是什么原因引起的| 青梅是什么意思| 10月12号是什么星座| 儿童鼻炎挂什么科| 审美观是什么意思| 排卵期和排卵日有什么区别| 精油是干什么用的| 美妙绝伦是什么意思| vc什么时候吃最好| 电脑长期不关机有什么影响| 经常喝藕粉有什么好处| 髓母细胞瘤是什么病| 中国第五大发明是什么| 无痕是什么意思| 和合是什么意思| 梅菜在北方叫什么菜| 活塞是什么意思| 前列腺是什么原因引起的| 什么叫紫癜| 什么食物| rosa是什么意思| 无意识是什么意思| mlb是什么牌子| 江与河有什么区别| 药物过敏用什么药| 梦见大蛇是什么预兆| 纯情什么意思| 炸薯条用什么粉| 梦见玉米是什么意思| 清炖排骨放什么调料| 乙肝通过什么传播| egg是什么意思| 金丝檀木是什么木头| 肾结石要注意什么| 睾丸为什么会痛| 花生不能和什么一起吃| 什么是华盖| 白粉病用什么药| 膝盖窝疼是什么原因| 子宫在肚脐眼什么位置| 迷你什么意思| 真实的印度是什么样的| 阴阳数字是什么数| 梦见买衣服是什么预兆| 氯偏高是什么原因| 洗衣机脱水是什么意思| 露从今夜白下一句是什么| 杏林春暖的杏林指什么| 乳头有点痛什么原因| 什么叫个人修养| 黄梅时节是什么季节| 肺部磨玻璃结节需要注意什么| 缠足是什么时候开始的| 尿液茶色是什么原因| 浙江有什么城市| 新生儿什么时候剪头发| 3月30日是什么星座| 梦见摘菜是什么意思| 感冒干咳无痰吃什么药| 鲭鱼是什么鱼| 脾气暴躁易怒是什么病| 什么是尿常规检查| 忧心忡忡是什么意思| 早泄要吃什么药| 乙肝125阳性是什么意思| 什么是熊猫血型| ECG是什么| vsop是什么意思| 清远有什么好玩的| 广州五行属什么| 寒风吹起细雨迷离是什么歌| 给男朋友买什么礼物比较好| 社保指的是什么| 喝什么去火效果最好| 什么环境唱什么歌原唱| 一什么月亮| 丝瓜和什么相克| 什么人不能吃蚕豆| 保险公司最怕什么投诉| 喉咙痛吃什么药好得最快| 沫沫是什么意思| 玛丽苏是什么意思| 痛风应该挂什么科| 脸色蜡黄是什么原因| 爬山有什么好处| 女人有腰窝意味着什么| 狗为什么喜欢吃骨头| 女性朋友生日送什么礼物好| 玫瑰花代表什么意思| 两鬓斑白是什么意思| 海怪是什么海鲜| 氧化铜什么颜色| 性早熟有什么危害| 猫离家出走预示着什么| 黄瓜敷脸有什么功效| 67是什么意思| 脑洞是什么意思| allan英文名什么意思| 桃不能和什么一起吃| 玉鸟吃什么饲料好| 免疫系统由什么组成| 肺结节挂什么科| 蘖是什么意思| 什么和什么不能一起吃| 12月是什么星座的| 劳改犯是什么意思| 菟丝子有什么功效| 九点到十点是什么时辰| 梦见小猪仔什么意思| 女性更年期在什么年龄段| 什么散步填词语| 香醋和陈醋有什么区别| 倒刺是什么原因引起的| 双手脱皮是什么原因引起的| 什么洗面奶祛痘| 爱之深恨之切是什么意思| 下巴下面长痣代表什么| 百度

习近平向世界发出邀约 开启“一带一路”北京新航程

百度   中共中央书记处书记、中央统战部部长尤权参加走访和座谈。

The word "probability" has been used in a variety of ways since it was first applied to the mathematical study of games of chance. Does probability measure the real, physical, tendency of something to occur, or is it a measure of how strongly one believes it will occur, or does it draw on both these elements? In answering such questions, mathematicians interpret the probability values of probability theory.

There are two broad categories[1][a][2] of probability interpretations which can be called "physical" and "evidential" probabilities. Physical probabilities, which are also called objective or frequency probabilities, are associated with random physical systems such as roulette wheels, rolling dice and radioactive atoms. In such systems, a given type of event (such as a die yielding a six) tends to occur at a persistent rate, or "relative frequency", in a long run of trials. Physical probabilities either explain, or are invoked to explain, these stable frequencies. The two main kinds of theory of physical probability are frequentist accounts (such as those of Venn,[3] Reichenbach[4] and von Mises)[5] and propensity accounts (such as those of Popper, Miller, Giere and Fetzer).[6]

Evidential probability, also called Bayesian probability, can be assigned to any statement whatsoever, even when no random process is involved, as a way to represent its subjective plausibility, or the degree to which the statement is supported by the available evidence. On most accounts, evidential probabilities are considered to be degrees of belief, defined in terms of dispositions to gamble at certain odds. The four main evidential interpretations are the classical (e.g. Laplace's)[7] interpretation, the subjective interpretation (de Finetti[8] and Savage),[9] the epistemic or inductive interpretation (Ramsey,[10] Cox)[11] and the logical interpretation (Keynes[12] and Carnap).[13] There are also evidential interpretations of probability covering groups, which are often labelled as 'intersubjective' (proposed by Gillies[14] and Rowbottom).[6]

Some interpretations of probability are associated with approaches to statistical inference, including theories of estimation and hypothesis testing. The physical interpretation, for example, is taken by followers of "frequentist" statistical methods, such as Ronald Fisher[dubiousdiscuss], Jerzy Neyman and Egon Pearson. Statisticians of the opposing Bayesian school typically accept the frequency interpretation when it makes sense (although not as a definition), but there is less agreement regarding physical probabilities. Bayesians consider the calculation of evidential probabilities to be both valid and necessary in statistics. This article, however, focuses on the interpretations of probability rather than theories of statistical inference.

The terminology of this topic is rather confusing, in part because probabilities are studied within a variety of academic fields. The word "frequentist" is especially tricky. To philosophers it refers to a particular theory of physical probability, one that has more or less been abandoned. To scientists, on the other hand, "frequentist probability" is just another name for physical (or objective) probability. Those who promote Bayesian inference view "frequentist statistics" as an approach to statistical inference that is based on the frequency interpretation of probability, usually relying on the law of large numbers and characterized by what is called 'Null Hypothesis Significance Testing' (NHST). Also the word "objective", as applied to probability, sometimes means exactly what "physical" means here, but is also used of evidential probabilities that are fixed by rational constraints, such as logical and epistemic probabilities.

It is unanimously agreed that statistics depends somehow on probability. But, as to what probability is and how it is connected with statistics, there has seldom been such complete disagreement and breakdown of communication since the Tower of Babel. Doubtless, much of the disagreement is merely terminological and would disappear under sufficiently sharp analysis.

—?Savage, 1954, p. 2[9]

Philosophy

edit

The philosophy of probability presents problems chiefly in matters of epistemology and the uneasy interface between mathematical concepts and ordinary language as it is used by non-mathematicians. Probability theory is an established field of study in mathematics. It has its origins in correspondence discussing the mathematics of games of chance between Blaise Pascal and Pierre de Fermat in the seventeenth century,[15] and was formalized and rendered axiomatic as a distinct branch of mathematics by Andrey Kolmogorov in the twentieth century. In axiomatic form, mathematical statements about probability theory carry the same sort of epistemological confidence within the philosophy of mathematics as are shared by other mathematical statements.[16][17]

The mathematical analysis originated in observations of the behaviour of game equipment such as playing cards and dice, which are designed specifically to introduce random and equalized elements; in mathematical terms, they are subjects of indifference. This is not the only way probabilistic statements are used in ordinary human language: when people say that "it will probably rain", they typically do not mean that the outcome of rain versus not-rain is a random factor that the odds currently favor; instead, such statements are perhaps better understood as qualifying their expectation of rain with a degree of confidence. Likewise, when it is written that "the most probable explanation" of the name of Ludlow, Massachusetts "is that it was named after Roger Ludlow", what is meant here is not that Roger Ludlow is favored by a random factor, but rather that this is the most plausible explanation of the evidence, which admits other, less likely explanations.

Thomas Bayes attempted to provide a logic that could handle varying degrees of confidence; as such, Bayesian probability is an attempt to recast the representation of probabilistic statements as an expression of the degree of confidence by which the beliefs they express are held.

Though probability initially had somewhat mundane motivations, its modern influence and use is widespread ranging from evidence-based medicine, through six sigma, all the way to the probabilistically checkable proof and the string theory landscape.

A summary of some interpretations of probability [2]
Classical Frequentist Subjective Propensity
Main hypothesis Principle of indifference Frequency of occurrence Degree of belief Degree of causal connection
Conceptual basis Hypothetical symmetry Past data and reference class Knowledge and intuition Present state of system
Conceptual approach Conjectural Empirical Subjective Metaphysical
Single case possible Yes No Yes Yes
Precise Yes No No Yes
Problems Ambiguity in principle of indifference Circular definition Reference class problem Disputed concept

Classical definition

edit

The first attempt at mathematical rigour in the field of probability, championed by Pierre-Simon Laplace, is now known as the classical definition. Developed from studies of games of chance (such as rolling dice) it states that probability is shared equally between all the possible outcomes, provided these outcomes can be deemed equally likely.[1] (3.1)

The theory of chance consists in reducing all the events of the same kind to a certain number of cases equally possible, that is to say, to such as we may be equally undecided about in regard to their existence, and in determining the number of cases favorable to the event whose probability is sought. The ratio of this number to that of all the cases possible is the measure of this probability, which is thus simply a fraction whose numerator is the number of favorable cases and whose denominator is the number of all the cases possible.

—?Pierre-Simon Laplace, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities[7]

?
The classical definition of probability works well for situations with only a finite number of equally-likely outcomes.

This can be represented mathematically as follows: If a random experiment can result in N mutually exclusive and equally likely outcomes and if NA of these outcomes result in the occurrence of the event A, the probability of A is defined by

?

There are two clear limitations to the classical definition.[18] Firstly, it is applicable only to situations in which there is only a 'finite' number of possible outcomes. But some important random experiments, such as tossing a coin until it shows heads, give rise to an infinite set of outcomes. And secondly, it requires an a priori determination that all possible outcomes are equally likely without falling in a trap of circular reasoning by relying on the notion of probability. (In using the terminology "we may be equally undecided", Laplace assumed, by what has been called the "principle of insufficient reason", that all possible outcomes are equally likely if there is no known reason to assume otherwise, for which there is no obvious justification.[19][20])

Frequentism

edit
?
For frequentists, the probability of the ball landing in any pocket can be determined only by repeated trials in which the observed result converges to the underlying probability in the long run.

Frequentists posit that the probability of an event is its relative frequency over time,[1] (3.4) i.e., its relative frequency of occurrence after repeating a process a large number of times under similar conditions. This is also known as aleatory probability. The events are assumed to be governed by some random physical phenomena, which are either phenomena that are predictable, in principle, with sufficient information (see determinism); or phenomena which are essentially unpredictable. Examples of the first kind include tossing dice or spinning a roulette wheel; an example of the second kind is radioactive decay. In the case of tossing a fair coin, frequentists say that the probability of getting a heads is 1/2, not because there are two equally likely outcomes but because repeated series of large numbers of trials demonstrate that the empirical frequency converges to the limit 1/2 as the number of trials goes to infinity.

If we denote by ? the number of occurrences of an event ? in ? trials, then if ? we say that ?.

The frequentist view has its own problems. It is of course impossible to actually perform an infinity of repetitions of a random experiment to determine the probability of an event. But if only a finite number of repetitions of the process are performed, different relative frequencies will appear in different series of trials. If these relative frequencies are to define the probability, the probability will be slightly different every time it is measured. But the real probability should be the same every time. If we acknowledge the fact that we only can measure a probability with some error of measurement attached, we still get into problems as the error of measurement can only be expressed as a probability, the very concept we are trying to define. This renders even the frequency definition circular; see for example “What is the Chance of an Earthquake?[21]

Subjectivism

edit

Subjectivists, also known as Bayesians or followers of epistemic probability, give the notion of probability a subjective status by regarding it as a measure of the 'degree of belief' of the individual assessing the uncertainty of a particular situation. Epistemic or subjective probability is sometimes called credence, as opposed to the term chance for a propensity probability. Some examples of epistemic probability are to assign a probability to the proposition that a proposed law of physics is true or to determine how probable it is that a suspect committed a crime, based on the evidence presented. The use of Bayesian probability raises the philosophical debate as to whether it can contribute valid justifications of belief. Bayesians point to the work of Ramsey[10] (p 182) and de Finetti[8] (p 103) as proving that subjective beliefs must follow the laws of probability if they are to be coherent.[22] Evidence casts doubt that humans will have coherent beliefs.[23][24] The use of Bayesian probability involves specifying a prior probability. This may be obtained from consideration of whether the required prior probability is greater or lesser than a reference probability[clarification needed] associated with an urn model or a thought experiment. The issue is that for a given problem, multiple thought experiments could apply, and choosing one is a matter of judgement: different people may assign different prior probabilities, known as the reference class problem. The "sunrise problem" provides an example.

Propensity

edit

Propensity theorists think of probability as a physical propensity, or disposition, or tendency of a given type of physical situation to yield an outcome of a certain kind or to yield a long run relative frequency of such an outcome.[25] This kind of objective probability is sometimes called 'chance'.

Propensities, or chances, are not relative frequencies, but purported causes of the observed stable relative frequencies. Propensities are invoked to explain why repeating a certain kind of experiment will generate given outcome types at persistent rates, which are known as propensities or chances. Frequentists are unable to take this approach, since relative frequencies do not exist for single tosses of a coin, but only for large ensembles or collectives (see "single case possible" in the table above).[2] In contrast, a propensitist is able to use the law of large numbers to explain the behaviour of long-run frequencies. This law, which is a consequence of the axioms of probability, says that if (for example) a coin is tossed repeatedly many times, in such a way that its probability of landing heads is the same on each toss, and the outcomes are probabilistically independent, then the relative frequency of heads will be close to the probability of heads on each single toss. This law allows that stable long-run frequencies are a manifestation of invariant single-case probabilities. In addition to explaining the emergence of stable relative frequencies, the idea of propensity is motivated by the desire to make sense of single-case probability attributions in quantum mechanics, such as the probability of decay of a particular atom at a particular time.

The main challenge facing propensity theories is to say exactly what propensity means. (And then, of course, to show that propensity thus defined has the required properties.) At present, unfortunately, none of the well-recognised accounts of propensity comes close to meeting this challenge.

A propensity theory of probability was given by Charles Sanders Peirce.[26][27][28][29] A later propensity theory was proposed by philosopher Karl Popper, who had only slight acquaintance with the writings of C.?S. Peirce, however.[26][27] Popper noted that the outcome of a physical experiment is produced by a certain set of "generating conditions". When we repeat an experiment, as the saying goes, we really perform another experiment with a (more or less) similar set of generating conditions. To say that a set of generating conditions has propensity p of producing the outcome E means that those exact conditions, if repeated indefinitely, would produce an outcome sequence in which E occurred with limiting relative frequency p. For Popper then, a deterministic experiment would have propensity 0 or 1 for each outcome, since those generating conditions would have same outcome on each trial. In other words, non-trivial propensities (those that differ from 0 and 1) only exist for genuinely nondeterministic experiments.

A number of other philosophers, including David Miller and Donald A. Gillies, have proposed propensity theories somewhat similar to Popper's.

Other propensity theorists (e.g. Ronald Giere[30]) do not explicitly define propensities at all, but rather see propensity as defined by the theoretical role it plays in science. They argued, for example, that physical magnitudes such as electrical charge cannot be explicitly defined either, in terms of more basic things, but only in terms of what they do (such as attracting and repelling other electrical charges). In a similar way, propensity is whatever fills the various roles that physical probability plays in science.

What roles does physical probability play in science? What are its properties? One central property of chance is that, when known, it constrains rational belief to take the same numerical value. David Lewis called this the Principal Principle,[1] (3.3 & 3.5) a term that philosophers have mostly adopted. For example, suppose you are certain that a particular biased coin has propensity 0.32 to land heads every time it is tossed. What is then the correct price for a gamble that pays $1 if the coin lands heads, and nothing otherwise? According to the Principal Principle, the fair price is 32 cents.

Logical, epistemic, and inductive probability

edit

It is widely recognized that the term "probability" is sometimes used in contexts where it has nothing to do with physical randomness. Consider, for example, the claim that the extinction of the dinosaurs was probably caused by a large meteorite hitting the earth. Statements such as "Hypothesis H is probably true" have been interpreted to mean that the (presently available) empirical evidence (E, say) supports H to a high degree. This degree of support of H by E has been called the logical, or epistemic, or inductive probability of H given E.

The differences between these interpretations are rather small, and may seem inconsequential. One of the main points of disagreement lies in the relation between probability and belief. Logical probabilities are conceived (for example in Keynes' Treatise on Probability[12]) to be objective, logical relations between propositions (or sentences), and hence not to depend in any way upon belief. They are degrees of (partial) entailment, or degrees of logical consequence, not degrees of belief. (They do, nevertheless, dictate proper degrees of belief, as is discussed below.) Frank P. Ramsey, on the other hand, was skeptical about the existence of such objective logical relations and argued that (evidential) probability is "the logic of partial belief".[10] (p 157) In other words, Ramsey held that epistemic probabilities simply are degrees of rational belief, rather than being logical relations that merely constrain degrees of rational belief.

Another point of disagreement concerns the uniqueness of evidential probability, relative to a given state of knowledge. Rudolf Carnap held, for example, that logical principles always determine a unique logical probability for any statement, relative to any body of evidence. Ramsey, by contrast, thought that while degrees of belief are subject to some rational constraints (such as, but not limited to, the axioms of probability) these constraints usually do not determine a unique value. Rational people, in other words, may differ somewhat in their degrees of belief, even if they all have the same information.

Prediction

edit

An alternative account of probability emphasizes the role of prediction – predicting future observations on the basis of past observations, not on unobservable parameters. In its modern form, it is mainly in the Bayesian vein. This was the main function of probability before the 20th century,[31] but fell out of favor compared to the parametric approach, which modeled phenomena as a physical system that was observed with error, such as in celestial mechanics.

The modern predictive approach was pioneered by Bruno de Finetti, with the central idea of exchangeability – that future observations should behave like past observations.[31] This view came to the attention of the Anglophone world with the 1974 translation of de Finetti's book,[31] and has since been propounded by such statisticians as Seymour Geisser.

Axiomatic probability

edit

The mathematics of probability can be developed on an entirely axiomatic basis that is independent of any interpretation: see the articles on probability theory and probability axioms for a detailed treatment.

See also

edit

Notes

edit
  1. ^ The taxonomy of probability interpretations given here is similar to that of the longer and more complete Interpretations of Probability article in the online Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. References to that article include a parenthetic section number where appropriate. A partial outline of that article:
    • Section 2: Criteria of adequacy for the interpretations of probability
    • Section 3:
      • 3.1 Classical Probability
      • 3.2 Logical Probability
      • 3.3 Subjective Probability
      • 3.4 Frequency Interpretations
      • 3.5 Propensity Interpretations

References

edit
  1. ^ a b c d Hájek, Alan (21 October 2002), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), Interpretations of Probability, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University
  2. ^ a b c de Elía, Ramón; Laprise, René (2005). "Diversity in interpretations of probability: implications for weather forecasting". Monthly Weather Review. 133 (5): 1129–1143. Bibcode:2005MWRv..133.1129D. doi:10.1175/mwr2913.1. S2CID?123135127. "There are several schools of thought regarding the interpretation of probabilities, none of them without flaws, internal contradictions, or paradoxes." (p 1129) "There are no standard classifications of probability interpretations, and even the more popular ones may suffer subtle variations from text to text." (p 1130)
  3. ^ Venn, John (1876). The Logic of Chance. London: MacMillan.
  4. ^ Reichenbach, Hans (1948). The theory of probability, an inquiry into the logical and mathematical foundations of the calculus of probability. University of California Press. English translation of the original 1935 German. ASIN: B000R0D5MS
  5. ^ Mises, Richard (1981). Probability, statistics, and truth. New York: Dover Publications. ISBN?978-0-486-24214-9. English translation of the third German edition of 1951 which was published 30 years after the first German edition.
  6. ^ a b Rowbottom, Darrell (2015). Probability. Cambridge: Polity. ISBN?978-0745652573.
  7. ^ a b Laplace, P. S., 1814, English edition 1951, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities, New York: Dover Publications Inc.
  8. ^ a b de Finetti, Bruno (1964). "Foresight: its Logical laws, its Subjective Sources". In Kyburg, H. E. (ed.). Studies in Subjective Probability. H. E. Smokler. New York: Wiley. pp.?93–158. Translation of the 1937 French original with later notes added.
  9. ^ a b Savage, L.J. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc. ISBN?978-0-486-62349-8. {{cite book}}: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help)
  10. ^ a b c Ramsey, F. P. (1931). "Chapter VII, Truth and Probability (1926)" (PDF). In Braithwaite, R. B. (ed.). Foundations of Mathematics and Other Logical Essays. London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co. pp.?156–198. Retrieved 15 August 2013. Contains three chapters (essays) by Ramsey. The electronic version contains only those three.
  11. ^ Cox, Richard Threlkeld (1961). The algebra of probable inference. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins Press.
  12. ^ a b Keynes, John Maynard (1921). A Treatise on Probability. MacMillan. Retrieved 15 August 2013.
  13. ^ Carnap, Rudolph (1950). Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Carnap coined the notion "probability1" and "probability2" for evidential and physical probability, respectively.
  14. ^ Gillies, Donald (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London New York: Routledge. ISBN?978-0415182768.
  15. ^ Fermat and Pascal on Probability (@ socsci.uci.edu)
  16. ^ Laszlo E. Szabo, A Physicalist Interpretation of Probability Archived 4 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine (Talk presented on the Philosophy of Science Seminar, E?tv?s, Budapest, 8 October 2001.)
  17. ^ Laszlo E. Szabo, Objective probability-like things with and without objective indeterminism, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (2007) 626–634 (Preprint)
  18. ^ Spanos, Aris (1986). Statistical foundations of econometric modelling. Cambridge New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN?978-0521269124.
  19. ^ Simon French; John Maule; Nadia Papamichail (2009). Decision Behaviour, Analysis and Support. Cambridge University Press. p.?221. ISBN?978-1-139-48098-7.
  20. ^ Nils-Eric Sahlin (2013). "2. On Higher Order Beliefs". In J. P. Dubucs (ed.). Philosophy of Probability. Springer. p.?30. ISBN?978-94-015-8208-7.
  21. ^ Freedman, David and Philip B. Stark (2003)"What is the Chance of an Earthquake?" Earthquake Science and Seismic Risk.
  22. ^ Jaynes, E. T. (2003). Probability theory the logic of science. Cambridge, UK New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. ISBN?978-0521592710.
  23. ^ Kahneman, Daniel (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. ISBN?978-0374275631. The book contains numerous examples of the difference between idealized and actual thought. "[W]hen called upon to judge probability, people actually judge something else and believe they have judged probability." (p 98)
  24. ^ Grove, William M.; Meehl, Paul E. (1996). "Comparative efficiency of informal (subjective, impressionistic) and formal (mechanical, algorithmic) prediction procedures: The clinical-statistical controversy" (PDF). Psychology, Public Policy, and Law. 2 (2): 293–332. CiteSeerX?10.1.1.471.592. doi:10.1037/1076-8971.2.2.293. Archived from the original (PDF) on 30 October 2011. Statistical decisions are consistently superior to the subjective decisions of experts.
  25. ^ Peterson, Martin (2009). An introduction to decision theory. Cambridge, UK New York: Cambridge University Press. p.?140. ISBN?978-0521716543.
  26. ^ a b Miller, Richard W. (1975). "Propensity: Popper or Peirce?". British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 26 (2): 123–132. doi:10.1093/bjps/26.2.123.
  27. ^ a b Haack, Susan; Kolenda, Konstantin, Konstantin; Kolenda (1977). "Two Fallibilists in Search of the Truth". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society. 51 (Supplementary Volumes): 63–104. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/51.1.63. JSTOR?4106816.
  28. ^ Burks, Arthur W. (1978). Chance, Cause and Reason: An Inquiry into the Nature of Scientific Evidence. University of Chicago Press. pp.?694 pages. ISBN?978-0-226-08087-1.
  29. ^ Peirce, Charles Sanders and Burks, Arthur W., ed. (1958), the Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce Volumes 7 and 8, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, also Belnap Press (of Harvard University Press) edition, vols. 7-8 bound together, 798 pages, online via InteLex, reprinted in 1998 Thoemmes Continuum.
  30. ^ Ronald N. Giere (1973). "Objective Single Case Probabilities and the Foundations of Statistics". Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. Vol.?73. Elsevier. pp.?467–483. doi:10.1016/S0049-237X(09)70380-5. ISBN?978-0-444-10491-5.
  31. ^ a b c Geisser, Seymour (1993). Predictive Inference. CRC Press. ISBN?978-0-412-03471-8.

Further reading

edit
  • Cohen, L (1989). An introduction to the philosophy of induction and probability. Oxford New York: Clarendon Press Oxford University Press. ISBN?978-0198750789.
  • Eagle, Antony (2011). Philosophy of probability?: contemporary readings. Abingdon, Oxon New York: Routledge. ISBN?978-0415483872.
  • Gillies, Donald (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London New York: Routledge. ISBN?978-0415182768. A comprehensive monograph covering the four principal current interpretations: logical, subjective, frequency, propensity. Also proposes a novel intersubective interpretation.
  • Hacking, Ian (2006). The emergence of probability?: a philosophical study of early ideas about probability, induction and statistical inference. Cambridge New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN?978-0521685573.
  • Paul Humphreys, ed. (1994) Patrick Suppes: Scientific Philosopher, Synthese Library, Springer-Verlag.
    • Vol. 1: Probability and Probabilistic Causality.
    • Vol. 2: Philosophy of Physics, Theory Structure and Measurement, and Action Theory.
  • Jackson, Frank, and Robert Pargetter (1982) "Physical Probability as a Propensity," No?s 16(4): 567–583.
  • Khrennikov, Andrei (2009). Interpretations of probability (2nd?ed.). Berlin New York: Walter de Gruyter. ISBN?978-3110207484. Covers mostly non-Kolmogorov probability models, particularly with respect to quantum physics.
  • Lewis, David (1983). Philosophical papers. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN?978-0195036466.
  • Plato, Jan von (1994). Creating modern probability?: its mathematics, physics, and philosophy in historical perspective. Cambridge England New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN?978-0521597357.
  • Rowbottom, Darrell (2015). Probability. Cambridge: Polity. ISBN?978-0745652573. A highly accessible introduction to the interpretation of probability. Covers all the main interpretations, and proposes a novel group level (or 'intersubjective') interpretation. Also covers fallacies and applications of interpretations in the social and natural sciences.
  • Skyrms, Brian (2000). Choice and chance?: an introduction to inductive logic. Australia Belmont, CA: Wadsworth/Thomson Learning. ISBN?978-0534557379.
edit
聚乙二醇400是什么 海啸是什么意思 人为什么要有性生活 子衿什么意思 驹是什么意思
大姨妈量多是什么原因 05是什么生肖 11月份生日是什么星座 孕妇吃葡萄对胎儿有什么好处 them什么意思
为什么睡不着觉会胡思乱想 妈祖是什么 1月7日是什么星座 查脂肪肝做什么检查 红薯是什么茎
马齿苋煮水喝有什么功效 什么是口爆 茵陈和什么泡水喝对肝脏最好 什么治便秘 人流需要准备什么
skg是什么品牌hcv7jop9ns7r.cn 拔牙前需要做什么检查bysq.com 利福喷丁和利福平有什么区别hcv9jop7ns4r.cn 调虎离山是什么意思hcv9jop6ns9r.cn 旅游穿什么鞋最舒服hcv9jop6ns6r.cn
膀胱炎是什么症状表现hcv8jop5ns0r.cn 孕妇喝椰子水有什么好处hcv9jop0ns6r.cn 狗狗窝咳吃什么药最好hcv8jop8ns4r.cn 路政属于什么单位hcv7jop9ns9r.cn 多发性脂肪瘤是什么原因造成的hcv7jop7ns1r.cn
怀孕排卵试纸显示什么hcv9jop0ns9r.cn 梦见上香是什么意思adwl56.com xg是什么意思hcv8jop3ns4r.cn 不丹为什么不和中国建交hcv8jop6ns4r.cn 总是想睡觉是什么原因hcv7jop6ns4r.cn
梦见别人家盖房子是什么意思hcv9jop6ns1r.cn 女人更年期有什么症状hcv8jop8ns9r.cn 黔驴技穷是什么意思hcv7jop9ns3r.cn 左腿麻木是什么征兆adwl56.com 感觉抑郁了去医院挂什么科wuhaiwuya.com
百度